raspuns la analiza r.j.reynolds

Upload: sabina-hondru

Post on 30-May-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    1/9

    Comments on Rhetorical Analysis Within aPragma-Dialectical FrameworkThe Case of R. J. Reynolds

    EUGENE GARVER

    Regents Professor of Philosophy

    Saint Johns University

    Collegeville MN 56321

    U.S.A.

    RHETORIC, DIALECTIC, AND DEMOCRACY

    Rhetorical Analysis Within a Pragma-Dialectical Framework raises three

    questions. First, what is the relation between the methods of winning a

    dispute and the methods of securing agreement studied in pragma-dialec-

    tics? What is the relation between rhetoric and dialectic? This is a question

    to which van Eemeren and Houtlosser offer a clear answer, but I will invite

    them to reconsider in light of my other two questions. Second, how do the

    methods of verbal manipulation in general, whether competitive or coop-

    erative, relate to the methods used to arrive at something greater than agree-

    ment, such as truth or the accurate representation of nature? This second

    question could be posed as the relation between dialectic and rhetoric and

    the methods of science. Third, discourse often has purposes that havenothing to do with resolving disputes, and which therefore do not reach

    the threshold at which dialectic, for van Eemeren and Houtlosser, begins.

    Often people speak merely to be heard, to express themselves and create

    their identities within a community. Just as I wonder about the relation

    between both rhetoric and dialectic and science, I wonder about their

    relation to purely expressive discourse, a connection perhaps hinted at

    in Aristotles discussion of epideictic rhetoric, but surely needing more

    analysis.

    With a little massaging, the question of the relation of dialectic to

    rhetoric can be seen as identical to that posed by MacIntyre about prac-

    tical reason in general: Both kinds of achievement, that of excellence and

    that of victory, will require effective practical reasoning; and it will beimportant to learn whether and, if so, how the kind of practical reasoning

    necessary for the achievement of excellence differs from that necessary

    for the achievement of victory.1 What is the relation between living up to

    the dialectical norms of reasonableness and communication and aiming at

    victory for oneself, ones clients, ones favored party or policy?

    The question of the relation between excellence and victory is especially

    urgent, I think, in considering van Eemeren and Houtlossers empirical

    Argumentation 14: 307314, 2000.

    2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    2/9

    example. There are implicit judgments concerning the audience, the effecton the audience, whether the appeal is successful and whether it should be

    successful. In a way it seems to me that van Eemeren and Houtlosser take

    for granted a rhetorical story that is itself divorced from dialectical con-

    siderations. They seem to think that rhetorical intentions and effects are

    fairly transparent, and need only be subject to dialectical judgment. I doubt

    that audiences are as deceived and manipulated as they make out although

    how either of us would prove such a thing is another question and wonder

    how the rhetoric of these advertisements would look under the more dialec-

    tical assumptions that audiences are perfectly aware of what is going on.

    The relation between reasonableness and victory might force us to redefine

    both those terms.

    And thus my third issue. I dont think that Reynolds is trying to foolanybody. (This doesnt mean that I have a higher opinion of their motives

    or purposes than van Eemeren and Houtlosser do.) I offer the competing

    hypothesis that Reynolds is aiming at the creation and presentation of a

    corporate identity, that of the upright, thoughtful corporation, albeit one

    engaged in selling a product of questionable value. Theyve given up on

    trying to show that cigarettes are not dangerous, and instead are trying to

    position themselves as corporate good citizens. Like van Eemeren and

    Houtlosser, I base my hypothesis on the assumption that the advertorials

    purpose must be connected to something it is doing reasonably well: Since

    it belonged to Reynolds dialectical commitments to make a real effort at

    convincing young people that they should not smoke, whereas Reynolds

    being a tobacco company cannot be expected to abandon altogether its

    rhetorical aim of persuading people to smoke, it may be assumed that some

    rhetorical maneuvering is going on. I disagree with the antecedent and

    the assumption of that implication, but agree that we can only infer purposes

    from how the appeal works. On my hypothesis, there is a sort of persua-

    sion going on, but no aim at resolving differences of opinion. Of course

    one can always reduce epideictic rhetoric to forensic, in this case by

    claiming that Reynolds is trying to establish one corporate identity and

    rebut another: Were good guys, not bad guys. But that does seem to be

    letting the theory lead the data.

    In the rest of these comments, I will try to understand the relation

    between rhetoric and dialectic, both understood as being bounded by both

    the more scientific or truth-oriented and more poetic or expression-oriented

    uses of language. A further feature of van Eemeren and Houtlossers pre-sentation is of interest. They make the dialectical task of resolving differ-

    ences of opinion equivalent to establishing methodically whether or not a

    standpoint is defensible against doubt or criticism. A couple of things are

    worth noting about this language. First, differences of opinion arrive fairly

    late in the process of inquiry, resolving doubts and solving problems. Giving

    an initial definition to the problem, gathering evidence, sorting through and

    judging beliefs, all these things are likely to occur before we have articu-

    308 EUGENE GARVER

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    3/9

    lated ideas explicitly enough to have a pair of opinions that we know aredifferent from one another. In fact, I wonder whether starting at differences

    of opinion does not arise from neglecting my second issue, the relation

    between methods of rhetoric and dialectic and scientific methods.

    Consider these two possible relations between dialectic and rhetoric.

    First, one could survey rhetoric and communication in general, and make

    dialectic a subset of rhetoric. One might decide, for example, that among

    the ways we influence audiences, rational discourse was particularly

    useful in coming to agreements, while emotional discourse was especially

    disruptive or agonistic. Dialectic would then be about rational communi-

    cation. Similarly, we might single out unconstrained or undistorted com-

    munication. I can read both the Platonic and the Aristotelian program this

    way, to find within the given practices of persuasion and teaching thoseadapted to get at agreement, progress, and truth.

    As I understand them, van Eemeren and Houtlosser take the opposite

    tack. Dialectic establishes norms instrumental in achieving this purpose

    [resolving differences of opinion] maintaining certain standards of rea-

    sonableness and expecting others to comply with the same critical stan-

    dards. Those norms by themselves never determine what anyone will say.

    They allow a certain freedom, and within that freedom lies the rhetorical

    opportunity to resolve the difference in their own favour. Rhetorical aims

    can, in principle, be realised within a dialectical framework.

    There is something else worth noting about this formulation of the

    dialectical project. Establishing methodically whether or not a standpoint

    is defensible against doubt or criticism presupposes a judicial or forensic

    model for rationality. We have a right to opinions only if we can justify

    them. The burden of proof is on the holder of the opinion. It is popular

    these days to blame everything on Descartes. His method of doubt was

    the tree of knowledge that introduced the sin of skepticism into the world,

    and so it has become natural for us to think that any opinion that is not

    justified is unjustified, that all opinions stand accused of being prejudices

    unless we can overcome that suspicion by showing that we are justified in

    holding the belief. Poppers theory of falsification fit in this mode of

    thought.

    For better or worse, I believe that Descartes as Satan wildly overesti-

    mates the power of philosophy in our lives. I agree that skepticism and

    the need to justify our opinions plays a major role in configuring our intel-

    lectual lives. I propose as a hypothesis that this presumption that all ourbeliefs need justification is a function of the democratic nature of our con-

    temporary conceptions of rationality. Since everyone has a voice, there

    would be anarchy and cacophony unless there were a means of silencing

    opinions that are not worth hearing. The method of justification and the

    method of doubt is precisely such a necessary means of silencing opinions

    that are not worth listening to. Starting with the equality of democratic

    voices, the problem becomes one of instituting a hierarchy of which voices

    COMMENTS ON RHETORICAL ANALYSIS 309

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    4/9

    are worth listening to and which not. The judicial model of reasoning is aresponse to that problem. Naturally, the problem with basing dialectic and

    rhetoric on the judicial model will be to make sense of the traditional delib-

    erative and epideictic functions.

    My correlation between justification as the primary function of rea-

    soning, both theoretical and practical reason, can best be seen by noting

    how absent justificatory reasoning is from ancient models of rationality.

    Moderns criticize ancient pictures of practical reason, of rhetoric and

    dialectic, for being aristocratic.2 There only gentlemen were allowed to

    speak. The aristocratic presumption is that speakers are worth listening to,

    both because they were probably intelligent and because they were almost

    certainly like us. The burden of proof, correspondingly, is on a challenger

    to show why a given speaker or opinion is wrong. If we restrict the fran-chise and have high costs of entry into a conversation, then justification

    becomes less crucial, and a less natural feature of conversation. If we open

    discourse to all, then each must pay a price by justifying whatever he or

    she has to say.

    I think that this difference between ancient and modern presuppositions

    about practical reason accounts for some interesting differences between

    van Eemeren and Houtlossers presentation of dialectic and rhetoric and

    Aristotles. One of the striking things about the Topics and theRhetoric is

    that the Topics is the much more confrontational and agonistic work, with

    a stress on strategies for winning, while the Rhetoric presupposes a much

    more cooperative relation between speakers and their audience. In dialectic,

    as in pragma-dialectics, there is no audience, only a pair of interlocutors.

    In rhetoric, there are no interlocutors, only a speaker and an audience.3 The

    tasks of both rhetoric and dialectic are different from their contemporary

    appearance because of the ancient aristocratic presumption. In theRhetoric,

    the aristocratic assumption is that speaker and hearer are engaged in a

    common enterprise of trying to find the best policy. Deliberative rhetoric,

    not judicial or forensic rhetoric, is the paradigm for practical reasoning.

    Persuading and giving good advice are linked together (I.8.1365b22). On

    any important decision we deliberate together because we do not trust our-

    selves (Ethics III.3.1112b1011). Make deliberation and not justification

    the model for practical reasoning, and rhetoric is no longer the manipula-

    tive one of the dialectic/rhetoric pair. Rhetoric is reasoning by a speaker

    directed at an audience, while dialectic concerns reasoning directed at

    an opponent. If I assert a given proposition, I am committed, in dialectic,to all its logical consequences. The Topics shows how to exploit this com-

    mitment by enabling dialectical arguers to trip up their opponents, by

    showing undesirable implications of their propositions, or to avoid being

    trapped. The Rhetoric sees the rhetorical situation not as a confrontation

    between opponents, as the Topics does, but as the construction of a rela-

    tionship between speaker and hearers. The aristocracy of the Topics comes

    in its source of opinions in those which commend themselves to all or to

    310 EUGENE GARVER

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    5/9

    the majority or to the wise that is to all of the wise or to the majority orto the most famous and distinguished of them (Topics I.1.100b2223).

    Dialectic can include conflict in ways that rhetoric cannot because

    dialectic is not practical. For Aristotle all practical conflict is stasis, a

    negative term. There is nothing of what Kenneth Burke called the delights

    of faction. Cicero aligned rhetorical and dialectical methods of arguing both

    sides of a question with the skeptical program from philosophical enlight-

    enment. Machiavelli read Livy as showing that factions led to stability

    and progress, and that insight into the value of faction led to later

    ideas that even truth could emerge from conflict, and eventually from the

    marketplace of ideas.4 But all that is much later than Aristotle. There are

    refutative topoi, but persuasion itself is not an agonistic activity, and

    dialectic not a practical one. This suggests that rhetoric and dialectic arerelated in more ways than van Eemeren and Houtlossers configuration that

    dialectic sets the norms within which rhetoric is free to operate. Pragma-

    dialectics may well be more suited to a democracy than were Aristotles

    methods. I am not upholding the existence of an Aristotelian alternative

    as a reason to suspect van Eemeren and Houtlosser so much as to put their

    project in context.

    Aristotle contrasts dialectic and rhetoric in another way. They are both

    universal faculties without the restricted subject-matter that a science

    has. But rhetoric is restricted to the subjects of deliberation, judicial

    disputes and epideictic situations. Dialectic has no such circumstantial

    limitation. I wonder, though, about the dialectic of van Eemeren and

    Houtlosser. And thus my second question at the beginning, about the

    relation between dialectic and scientific method. Is there is a method for,

    as they say, resolving differences of opinion? Is it the same method

    which allows us to resolve our differences over whether scientific biology

    and/or creationism should be taught in public schools, disputes about

    gradualism vs. punctuated equilibrium, whether individual organisms or

    genes are the unit of selection and evolution, and over whether modern

    evolutionary theory is compatible with divine revelation? Or is dialectic

    restricted to the subjects on which democratic disagreement is allowed?

    The pseudo-AugustinesRhetoric says that rhetoric is about subjects about

    which we should be ashamed not to have an opinion. (See Gorgias 452de,

    Protagoras 318e319a.) Does dialectic have a subject-matter delimited in

    this way, even if not delimited by the principles that make a domain into

    a science? Or is dialectic about settling all sorts of differences of opinion?Is there a difference between negotiation and inquiry? Is there a differ-

    ence between aiming at agreement and aiming at truth?5

    To begin with, I suggest that the story that van Eemeren and Houtlosser

    draw from Toulmin, that the triumph of scientific method drew rhetoric

    and dialectic apart, is too simple. As they note, as dialectic disappears from

    the intellectual scene, logic and rationality itself become identified with

    scientific method and the development of method itself is another part

    COMMENTS ON RHETORICAL ANALYSIS 311

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    6/9

    of that story that needs to be told and so rhetoric becomes style andarrangement, and deception. Missing from that story is the fact that when

    dialectic is about methods of securing agreement and resolving disputes,

    the relation between whatever agreement we come up with and truth seems

    to become secondary. If dialectic as a means for resolving differences of

    opinion has nothing to do with truth, then its function is more limited than

    van Eemeren and Houtlosser suggest.

    I am not suggesting that we should go back to Aristotle. I do not think

    we ever have that kind of freedom to choose philosophical models of ratio-

    nality. I think that van Eemeren and Houtlosser are right to make practical

    reason basically a matter of justification. Democracy itself requires a

    hermeneutics of suspicion and a method of doubt. Deliberation becomes

    colored by this democratic requirement and its judicial model. Instead ofa problem-solving activity, deliberation becomes ideologized into another

    forum of resolving differences of opinion. Thus, in the Prometheus myth

    in Platos Protagoras, everyone gets to speak in political deliberation

    because the assumption is that everyone has something worth saying. In

    contemporary democratic deliberation, everyone gets to speak because

    everyone has a right to speak. Aristotles famous argument in favor of

    democratic deliberation in Politics III says nothing about rights and nothing

    about resolving differences of opinion:

    It is possible that the many, though not individually good men, yet when they come

    together may be better, not individually, but collectively, than those who are so, just as

    public dinners to which many contribute are better than those supplied at one mans

    cost; for where there are many, each individual, it may be argued, has some portion of

    virtue and wisdom, and when they have come together, just as the multitude becomes a

    single man with many feet and many hands and many senses, so also it becomes one

    personality as regards the moral and intellectual faculties (III.11.1281b110; cf.

    13.1283b2734).6

    Moreover, it makes sense for democratic methods for practical reason to

    search for rules for resolving disputes, instead of means and resources, such

    as the virtues, more suited to aristocratic conceptions of practical reason.

    Thus dialectic is favored over rhetoric. Rules make morality more demo-

    cratic. When the moral virtues are political virtues they depend on a polit-

    ical community of friendship and homonoia, irreducible to law while the

    democratic morality of rights and rules is codifiable. The companion charge

    to Aristotles ethics being aristocratic is that modern morality is legalistic.

    Open communities and their corresponding moralities must be legalistic.Only closed communities with tacit knowledge virtue is acting as the

    phronimos would act can be communities of virtue.

    The relations between democracy and scientific method are manifold,

    but I wonder if consideration of van Eemeren and Houtlossers paper hasnt

    led to an unexplored relation between them. I agree that something like van

    Eemeren and Houtlossers sense of dialectic is necessary for democracies

    to function. But for dialectic to do its work, it cannot be a universal method,

    312 EUGENE GARVER

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    7/9

    and in particular can function only against a background of a distinctscientific method. The growth and success of science makes democracy

    possible in the following way.7 Democracy, as a method of deliberation

    that centers on van Eemeren and Houtlossers sense of dialectic and

    rhetoric, is possible only if methods of resolving differences are segregated

    from methods of discovering and establishing truth. Of course, even in

    ancient Greece, as the Prometheus myth itself illustrates, not all questions

    were open for democratic deliberation. Architects and generals made

    professional decisions that were not subject to majority vote. But when

    everyone has a right to speak, and when everyone is expanded through the

    succession of extensions of the franchise, the decisions available for demo-

    cratic deliberation are restricted to those where we value, or can afford,

    agreement rather than truth. Democracy and democratic deliberation arepossible only when science is secure and successful enough that its work

    is left untouched by deliberation, dialectic and rhetoric. For just one

    example, when Rawls talks about reflective equilibrium, a general method

    for resolving political differences, all ones opinions are available for com-

    promise and negotiation. But that set of opinions does not include the truths

    of neoclassical economics. Rawls holds them as fixed and not subject to

    debate. I do not offer that example in criticism of Rawls, but rather as a

    symptom of the connection between science and democracy. It is no

    accident that van Eemeren and Houtlosser rehabilitate dialectic by limiting

    it to agreement rather than truth. But such an art of dialectic can function

    only against a background of settled science and scientific method. Science

    makes the world safe for democracy.

    NOTES

    1 Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, University of Notre Dame Press,

    1988, p. 28. For one example, see H. Jefferson Powell, The Moral Tradition of American

    Constitutionalism, A Theological Interpretation, Durham and London: Duke University Press,

    1993, p. 119. Largely because of the slavery issue, individual legal arguments and judicial

    decisions in the antebellum period are often marked by conflict between the pursuit of the

    internal goods of the tradition (logical argument, textual fidelity, and so on) and the external

    goods of maintaining the Union and the institutional power and prestige of the courts.2 Nothing in this contrast of ancient and modern denies the democratic origins of ancient

    rhetoric, for which see, e.g., Josiah Ober, Political Dissent in Democratic Athens: Intellectual

    Critics of Popular Rule, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998 and Harvey Yunis,

    Taming Democracy: Models of Political Rhetoric in Classical Athens, Ithaca and London:

    Cornell University Press, 1996.3 Plato shows how to complicate these contrasts. In the Protagoras, after the Simonides

    interlude, the audience becomes an interlocutor as one of the speakers in an imaginary

    dialogue with Socrates and Protagoras together as the other party. For Plato, dialectic must

    neglect the audience because only between speakers can there be the friendship necessary

    for the discovery of truth. Modern science discovers how one can have truth without friend-

    ship, a very democratic procedure.4 Nor did the sophists advance the idea that truth emerges from the conflict of opinions,

    COMMENTS ON RHETORICAL ANALYSIS 313

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    8/9

    and so that factions were good things. They simply thought that competition was a given,and they were going to help their clients get the best out of it.5 One can resist the reduction of inquiry to negotiation and rationality to civility either by

    distinguishing science from both rhetoric and dialectic, or by showing how scientific ratio-

    nality infects rhetoric and dialectic too, so that they are not only about agreement and decision

    but agreement and decision oriented to truth. Rather than inquiry being a form of negotia-

    tion, Aristotle ultimately sees negotiation as a form of inquiry.6 For similar claims, see Politics III.3.11.1282a14, a3441, III.13.1287b2328, IV.4.

    1292a1014. See alsoMetaphysics II.993b16: No one is able to attain the truth adequately,

    while, on the other hand, we do not collectively fail, but every one says something true about

    the nature of things, and while individual we contribute little or nothing to the truth, by the

    union of all a considerable amount is amassed. Therefore, since the truth seems to be like

    the proverbial door, which no one can fail to hit, in this respect it must be easy, but the fact

    that we can have a whole truth and not a particular part we aim at shows the difficulty of

    it. III.15.1286a2731: When the law cannot determine a point at all, or not well, should

    the one best man or should all decide? According to our present practice assemblies meet,sit in judgment, deliberate, and their judgments all relate to individual cases. Now any

    member of the assembly, taken separately, is certainly inferior to the wise man. But the same

    is made up of many individuals. And as a feast to which all the guests contribute is better

    than a banquet furnished by a single man, so a multitude is a better judge of many things

    than any individual.

    Yack, 1993, p. 167. Although Aristotle does claim genuine knowledge of the human

    good and does construct a utopian regime in which the human good is best realized, he

    never suggests that we should measure the justice of laws and public acts by asking how

    close they come to realizing the states of affairs found in the best regime.7 Historically, there are two principal preconditions for democracy. I focus here on the rise

    of science. But equally the retreat of religion is a necessary condition for democracy. This

    can be seen in Spinozas Tractatus Theologico-Politicus and the Political Treatise, and in

    Humes essay on Parties in General. For the latter, see my Why Pluralism Now? Monist

    73 (1990): 388410.

    314 EUGENE GARVER

  • 8/9/2019 Raspuns La Analiza R.J.reynolds

    9/9